Elsewhere, I
have argued that all questions relating to facts about the real world can be
addressed by scientific method, and that if we are truly interested in
approaching the correct answers to such questions, then we are foolish to rely
on any other method. One important class of questions most people, including,
it seems, many scientists, think can’t be answered scientifically concerns how
we should determine our moral goals. It seems to me that only a modest amount
of reflection is required to dispel this pervasive myth.
The purpose of
science is to provide ever more precise plausibility estimates for propositions
concerning the sate of reality. Rightness and wrongness, though, are not among
the objective properties matter. To attribute ideas such as good and evil to external nature is to commit the mind projection fallacy – to assume that
properties of our internal model of reality correspond to properties of the
reality.
Consider that
classic image of natural selection in action, a lion chasing a zebra, with
intention to devour it. There is no sense in which we can apply concepts of
right and wrong, or good and evil to this situation. It is not evil that the
zebra suffers agony at the teeth and claws of the lion, any more than it is
evil if the lion suffers misery and protracted death from starvation. What we
have here is simply chemistry unfolding in a mildly interesting manner – genes
either preparing to replicate or losing the opportunity to do so. Furthermore,
to assert that humanity is something more than this mildly interesting
chemistry is certainly not founded on any rational procedure.
That we
experience pain, misery, and torment are mind-bending, heart-wrenching facts
about life, for us. But the universe does not
care. There is no sense in which these values can be attributed as properties
of the universe. To the universe, we are just yet more chemistry, a collection
of slightly unusual aggregates of matter that dance about on the surface of an
otherwise insignificant chunk of rock, one of an estimated 1020
planets in the known universe.
It is not that
natural selection, or the universe, wants us to maximize our happiness. It is
simply that a genome capable of generating an algorithm for producing the
sensation of such a value apparently gains an additional advantage in the struggle to
preserve its information. In fact, it is possible that our genes would prefer
us to be unhappy – its that ‘Oh shit, I’d better not do that again,’ effect
that seems to give the mechanism its selective advantage. If you are really
happy, then you will stop striving to do better, and your cousin, who has the
‘try harder’ mutation, will walk all over you.
This might seem
an odd line of reasoning, given the agenda I have defined in the opening
paragraph, but we have already established enough to demonstrate undeniably
that morality concerns matters of fact with objective truth, and that there is
a clear scientific route to take in pursuit of those truths. In fact, it was formulating an argument along the above lines, a couple of years ago, while trying to refute the conclusions of this infamous TED talk by Sam Harris, that I came to my current understanding of the topic. I had formerly assumed the standard position, that science can not specify moral goals. (Harris's ideas were shortly afterward expanded to book length, in 'The moral landscape.')
The above
paragraphs can be condensed into one very simple statement, one of only two
simple principles (the other being a trivial tautology) needed to establish the
validity of a potential science-based morality:
Principle (1):
‘Good’ and ‘evil’ are concepts with no reality outside minds.
To obtain
principle (2), we simply must remind ourselves what the word ‘morality’ means:
Principle (2):
Morality is doing what is good.
Principle (1)
states that good and evil do not exist outside minds. This does not, however,
mean that they have no objective existence. Since they are words used to
describe our mental reactions to different situations, then it is clear that
they are values with some physical representation inside our minds. We forget this too easily, partly, perhaps, because of
the scientific doctrine of objectivity, which typically means that our mental
state should be kept as separate from the system under study and the process of
gathering evidence as possible. This is normally a good principle – we have
dozens of documented cognitive biases that make it essential to eliminate the
influence of our preconceptions and emotional responses when conducting
science. But what happens when our minds are the system under study? Crude
application of the doctrine of objectivity can cause confusion. A mental state is
not something lacking objective reality, as we might erroneously infer from
this doctrine – we are, after all, physical entities. Our brains are made of
atoms, and our thoughts and emotions necessarily correspond to specific
configurations of matter and energy in our neurological hardware.
Because the
mental states pertaining to right and wrong have no existence outside minds,
then we can be confident that anything there is to be known about them can only
be discovered by looking inside minds.
We already have
instrumentation capable of measuring important data pertaining to mental states
(functional magnetic resonance imaging being currently very popular), and since
enormous improvements in this technology are quite likely, then it is in
principle possible that we will at some time be capable of generating extremely
detailed scientific information on the subject of what stimuli correspond to
value judgements of right and wrong. I believe we already know enough to make a
highly functional first approximation.
We can correlate
measured mental states with people’s self-reported happiness, and other
surrogate measures, and we can stochastically map those mental states to the
stimuli that caused them. And since morality is simply doing good, we can
scientifically optimize our behaviour to maximize the occurrence of the
relevant mental states (experienced good), and scientific morality has in
principle entirely achieved it objectives.
Objections:
1.
The value problem
Goes something
like this: ‘How can we know that we should value wellbeing? Surely science
can’t tell us what to value, can it?’ These questions are confused. It is not
the goal for science to tell us what to value (not at the highest level, at
least). We want science to tell us what we actually do value. Note that value
and perceived good are completely synonymous, and there is no good other than the perceived kind. Similarly, the declaration that
we value wellbeing is another unavoidable tautology. We are talking about
measuring the perception of value in people’s brains, and trying to bring about
the circumstances that enhance the frequency of the observed mental states.
There is no ambiguity about whether or not we should do this: to say you don’t
value wellbeing, or happiness, or whatever is good would be self contradictory. Goodness is the extent to which something is appropriate, so there is no sense asking why we should do good: you might as well ask for proof that we should do what we should do.
2.
The measurement problem
Another commonly
voiced objection is: ‘How do we know we are measuring the right thing?’ We
can’t, but this does not nullify the existence of objective answers to
questions about morality. While being one of the commonest complaints against
objective morality, it is also one of the most unfair and idiotic. The same
objection applies to all of science. Science systematically evaluates
knowledge, in the form of direct sensory experience, in order to ascribe
probabilities to propositions about phenomena in nature. There is no direct
logical link between these sensory experiences and the phenomena we wish to
learn about - the actual truth values of these scientific propositions remain
forever obscured. This is exactly why probabilities constitute the ultimate
expression of our knowledge.
Consider an
apparently simple physical concept, temperature, and its measurement. The
original concept of temperature related entirely to a subjective experience –
if I put my hand on something hot, it feels hot, and this is how we originally
knew that something possessed a high temperature. (There are occasionally other
indicators as well, such as combustion, but all of these come down to
subjective experience in the end.) At some point, a clever person realized that
they could correlate these subjective symptoms of high temperature with the
expansion of a fluid in a narrow glass capillary. The first accurate
thermometer was born. How did they know that the rising fluid in the thermometer
corresponded to the same phenomenon they were experiencing when they felt an
object’s high temperature? They did carefully controlled experiments. But
ultimately, they had no way of knowing for certain.
As science
advanced, people realized that the assumed linear thermal expansion upon which
calibration of these simple thermometers is based breaks down at extreme
temperatures, and new technologies were developed to overcome the difficulty,
giving progressively more accurate measurements, and greater ranges of
validity.
Now note a
curious thing. Even with the crude glass capillary style of thermometer,
subjective experience is no longer the ultimate arbiter of temperature. A
concept originally devised to account for subjective experience was found (with
very high probability) to have an underlying physical mechanism that could be
characterized accurately with external instruments. Given two objects of
similar temperature, even a practiced human can easily be mistaken as to which
one is hotter. A precise thermometer, however, will not be mistaken, and will
give a result in direct conflict with the human. There has never been a serious
suggestion, however, that such occurrences invalidate the use of the
thermometer – instead, it is obvious that subjective experience is not
perfectly correlated with the physics that it tries to characterize. So it is
with feelings of wellbeing, and we must expect that neuroscience will quickly
advance to a point where many kinds of mental states can be determined far more
accurately than using a person’s self-reported state of mind (I would think
this condition already holds in several cases). There is no contradiction here,
as these mental states are real states of matter inside the substrates of minds
(usually brains). People can be mistaken about what they want.
3.
The persuasion problem
You can not
persuade somebody who is committed to the contrary view that wellbeing should
be valued. Does this mean that value is not an objective property of reality, or
that wellbeing can’t be the basic guide of morality? Of course not. That
wellbeing is valued is a tautology, as pointed out already. Being well, happy,
and satisfied is just the fortunate condition of possessing much of what you
value. That some people will not accept this analytical truth is a consequence
of the failure of their minds to operate efficiently. The often-quoted fact
that nearly half of all Americans do not accept the theory of evolution (link) has absolutely no impact on the validity of this model of how life reaches is
various states of diversity.
4.
What about psychopaths?
Is one morality
less true than another? Since morality is rationally figuring out how to
improve you state of happiness, no, symmetry demands that there is no
privileged authority on ethical behaviour.
But this implies
that psychopaths are also moral, right? Wrong, actually. It doesn’t imply that
anybody’s actions are moral, the requirement for rationality needs to be met.
Ultimately,
though, it is possible to imagine that there might be psychopaths who are perfectly
rational, and highly successful at maximizing their own fulfillment by acting
abhorrently to others. This still poses no real philosophical problem.
Psychopaths are outnumbered by an estimated 99 to 1 (in the US), so our morality trumps
theirs (actually, by those odds there seems a reasonable chance that some
psychopath will read this). Our (non-psychopathic) morality dictates that we do
what we can to limit their harmful tendencies. Even the psychopaths, by the
way, presumably do not want to be the victims of other psychopaths.
Additionally, a person can be mistaken about what their highest-level desires are. A person can be mistaken about the relationship between their lower-level desires and their ultimate goals, and most obviously, a person can be mistaken about the likely outcomes of their actions and what will be the results on their happiness. This means that even the ethics of a person acting rationally can be improved by furnishing then with more accurate facts.
All rational, equally well-informed behaviour is equally valid. Pretending that
there is something wrong with this principle, because it fails to
unambiguously condemn the foul actions of sadists is to ignore the obvious
truth that the appropriateness of one’s conduct is tautologically determined by
its capacity to generate mental states corresponding to appropriateness.
Furthermore, it is to insist that room be left open for some principle that, besides being wrong, will, almost by definition, not have the slightest impact on the behaviour of
psychopaths, who don’t seem to care what is expected of them by moral
philosophers.
5.
Lack of uniqueness
It is not clear
that there is a unique solution to the mathematical problem of maximizing
wellbeing. There may very well be some upper limit to how happy I can be, and
there may be many ways to arrive at that upper limit (but I’m not holding my
breath). This does nothing to negate the arguments laid out. Whatever class of conditions enables that upper limit to be attained, it is determined by objective facts about nature.
6.
Lack of universality
Different people
have different values, but as discussed at number 4, this poses no
philosophical threat to my thesis. Human beings, however, as members of a
single species, are more similar than we are different, so substantial overlap
between the ambitions of different individuals is to be highly expected.
Furthermore, direct commonality of goals can also be confidently predicted –
what’s good for you is good for me. The fact that our morality is ultimately
selfish does not need to stand in the way of a high degree of cooperation.
A society that
protects all people indiscriminately is very likely to protect me. A global
economy that flourishes has a good chance to be one in which I am not poor. A
society where learning and technology thrive is a good choice if I hope to have
a comfortable life, and complex technology is very difficult to attain without
close, structured cooperation between thousands of people.
In ‘The selfish
gene,’ Richard Dawkins has written much on how cooperative behaviour emerges
naturally among selfish agents, by mechanisms such as kin selection and
reciprocal altruism. He has also made a nice TV documentary, 'Nice guys finish first,' on the
topic, specifically to answer critics who unintelligently insisted that selfish
genes imply selfish people. Further, by initiating the concept of memes, he
has made it clear how human behaviour has evolved far beyond the consequences
of mere population genetics. We are not bound by genetic evolution anymore, and
cultural innovations capable of enhancing mutually beneficial technological and
social developments are to be positively expected.
7.
Which utility function?
There are
different ways to model value, e.g. a rational utility function, or prospect
theory (which more accurately models how humans naturally assess utility), but which one
should we use? The answer is simple: the one that works. Briefly, (a bit late
for that, I think) the point is that one day we might be smart enough to measure
utility directly, by studying the physical states of brains (and potentially
other substrates supporting minds).
8.
Kahneman’s alternate selves
Daniel Kahneman
and coworkers have repeatedly shown that there are different measures of
happiness within a single human mind (see this TED talk, for example): the experiencing self, and the
remembering self. Which one is correct for our purposes? Again, (and again very
briefly) the one that works. Measure the success of basing your behaviour on
one choice and compare to outcomes with the other choice, then adopt the policy
that produces the optimal result.
9.
How does wellbeing aggregate?
Assuming that my
happiness is affected by some measure of global happiness (see number 6), how
should we combine happiness measures for different people? Should they be
added, multiplied, or what? Isn’t the final choice ultimately arbitrary?
No, its not.
Once more, measure the outcome of some likely aggregation function and compare
it with other candidates. Did we need some a-priori basis for accurately combining temperatures in order to accept its
validity as a physical concept? Did the cave man need to know that two objects
placed in contact would equilibrate to some intermediate temperature, rather
than their temperatures adding algebraically, in order to know that the embers
in his fire were hot?
The text seems to use the term «objective» in two different ways (a) concerning objective facts/properties about reality ("objective reality", "objective existence", "objective facts"), and (b) knowledge that is independent of individual mental states ("objective answers", "objective morality").
ReplyDeleteSentence of type (a) are either tautological (external reality simply is whatever it is), or a subtle case of the mind-projection fallacy (can we really state that external reality is objective or anything else?). I'm not sure about this, but I prefer to use the word 'objective' in the (b) sense, ie, only to knowledge about stuff, not to the stuff itself.
In a sense it is more compatible with the current use of subjectivity: knowledge that depends on individual mental states. Different types of knowledge should be seen not in boolean terms (is it objective or subjective?) but as points in a continuum between two extremes: total objectivity and total subjectivity. Of course, these two extremes really can never be reach. We can only approach them. This perspective could also provide for some dose of humility even to the practitioners of the hard core knowledge of Math.
Using the term is this two-fold manner can also be the cause of some current philosophical confusions (eg, many mathematicians are math realists, a belief that I really cannot understand smart people can defend without assuming they are mixing these two meanings of objectivity).
Cheers,
I took a bit of a conscious gamble with the use of the words 'objective' and 'subjective.' Perhaps this wasn't wise, despite devoting one paragraph to trying to dispel the confusion surrounding them. Certainly there is a lot of philosophical error due to these terms, and maybe they would have been best avoided.
DeleteEvery time I use the word 'objective', it's in the sense of something that is true, regardless of what we know or suspect about it. Knowledge, by definition can never be independent of mental states, and I don't use the word like that.
A few times, in the early paragraphs, I used words like 'nature' and 'reality,' meaning external nature, outside our minds (e.g. 'There is no sense in which these values can be attributed as properties of the universe.'), but I am trusting people to understand my shorthand.
It seems to me, the biggest source of confusion results from the assumption that its objective XOR subjective. Statements about mental states are of course subjective, but this doesn't prevent them being also objectively either true or false. Indeed, they must be.
I agree with your point about math-realism. Several people I otherwise respect greatly steadfastly stick to to position that numbers are real, despite a complete inability to meet the simple challenge posed by the question: "where are they then?"
"Ultimately, though, it is possible to imagine that there might be psychopaths who are perfectly rational, and highly successful at maximizing their own fulfillment by acting abhorrently to others. This still poses no real philosophical problem. Psychopaths are outnumbered by an estimated 99 to 1 (in the US), so our morality trumps theirs (actually, by those odds there seems a reasonable chance that some psychopath will read this). Our (non-psychopathic) morality dictates that we do what we can to limit their harmful tendencies. Even the psychopaths, by the way, presumably do not want to be the victims of other psychopaths"
ReplyDeleteSo morality comes down to a majority vote?
Strictly, no, morality is personal. Basic symmetry considerations show that there can be no privileged position when discerning moral truth, other than the quality of one's facts and inferences. (The search for the one divine source of universal moral truth is one of the great ongoing blunders of humanity. Dating back millennia before anybody even figured out that they should wash the shit off their hands before eating, perhaps its a quest we are at last nearly ready to shake off.)
DeleteIn practice, yes, for 2 reasons, as explained: as a single species and as entities that benefit from cooperation, humans tend to have highly overlapping goals. Anybody who's ambitions conflict sufficiently with those typically common goals has the right to expect trouble (and if being reasonable, should probably update their own goals accordingly).
Great to see a post about these things. I just read The Moral Landscape and am a fan of Sam Harris.
ReplyDelete